ECPR

Install the app

Install this application on your home screen for quick and easy access when you’re on the go.

Just tap Share then “Add to Home Screen”

ECPR

Install the app

Install this application on your home screen for quick and easy access when you’re on the go.

Just tap Share then “Add to Home Screen”

Methods in Normative Political Theory

Political Methodology
Political Theory
Social Justice
Analytic
Methods
S39
Keith Dowding
Australian National University
Adrian Blau
Kings College London


Abstract

Rationale There is a great deal written about methods in political science, but relatively little about methods in political philosophy. To some extent that is changing with the methods revolution extending its reach into normative political theory. We propose to open up that debate with Panels on methods of normative analysis. There are a number of questions to be posed. What are the criteria for good normative analysis in political theory? What precisely is the distinction between moral and political philosophy? What counts as evidence in normative theorizing? Do the methods of normative theory determine the sorts of answers we get? A principle method of political theory is conceptual analysis. Defining political terms and then subjecting rival definitions to critical appraisal is a staple of analytic political theory. But is the process of providing necessary and sufficient conditions for determining the extension of these terms sufficient to clarify political argument? Are normative terms instead necessarily fuzzy or subject only to ‘family resemblances’? What do we make of results from formal theory that some terms (such as ‘freedom of choice’) have contradictory normative desiderata? Does game theory help us clarify our normative intuitions? Another traditional method of theorizing is the use of thought experiments and intuition pumps. Here, in Rawls’s terms, moral intuitions, or moral judgements are used to reflect upon theory, and theory to reflect upon intuitions, each being changed or shaped until they are brought into ‘reflective equilibrium’. But what is the character of moral intuitions as evidence? If moral theory is supposed to guide moral thought, how can moral intuitions be used to ‘test’ theory. And why should we think that the process of reflective equilibrium will bring about one equilibrium? There might be multiple equilibriums. Do we have any ideas about equilibrium selection strategies? In grand theory different methods are used to constrain personal interests – different ‘veils of ignorance’ in contract theory; impartial spectator methods; ‘reasonable rejection’ and ‘public reason’. Are the answers method-driven with different methods leading to different conclusions; or can we derive the same conclusions from different methods, meaning our arguments are conclusion-driven? Is normative theory simply a game whereby we provide post hoc reasons for conclusions already intuited? Exegesis of historic texts in political philosophy, either in the historical context of their authors or as a timeless conversation, is typically construed to be helpful for philosophers. Can we construe analysis of such texts to be a method of political philosophy? Is it a valuable exercise for theorists concerned with contemporary affairs? Does historical analysis show that modern theorizing is based on the interest rhetoric of the past or can we throw off historical shackles? The ideal/non-ideal debate revolves around the logical coherence of two different ways of thinking about political philosophy. While the debate centres on the distinction between the choices that should ideally be available to us and the choices that are actually available to us, the constraint of empirical patterns (e.g. the unravelling of idyllic visions of centralized economies into myopic dictatorships) on the specification of the ideals at the heart of the dispute hasn’t yet been made clear. Can we learn about the stability, unintended consequences, and metaphysical possibility of social ideals by way of empirical investigation? To what extent are the methods of empirical scientists also the methods of political theorists? Might the revolution in empirical methods provide the bridge for a revolution in methods of political philosophy? Co-Chairs Keith Dowding Australian National University keith.dowding@anu.edu.au Adrian Blau King’s College London adrian.blau@kcl.ac.uk
Code Title Details
P061 Conceptual Analysis View Panel Details
P068 'Continental’ Methods of Political Theorizing View Panel Details
P168 Historical Approaches to Political Theory View Panel Details
P178 Ideal and Non-Ideal Political Theory View Panel Details
P209 Intuitions, Norms and Thought Experiments View Panel Details
P350 Realist Political Theory View Panel Details